David F. Ericson. The Debate over Slavery:
Antislavery and Proslavery Liberalism in Antebellum America.
New York: New York University Press, 2000. 241 pages.
Near
the end of The Debate over Slavery, David F. Ericson quotes from a Civil
War speech delivered by Abraham Lincoln in which the president noted, the
world has never had a good definition of the word liberty
. We all declare
for liberty; but in using the same word we do not all mean the same thing
(p. 157). This debate over contrasting definitions of liberty, never settled
satisfactorily even after the war, continues to resonate for citizens and scholars.
Ericson contributes to this discussion with a careful analysis of antislavery
and proslavery arguments in antebellum America. The author provocatively contends
that both positions remained firmly embedded in the intellectual and ideological
traditions of American liberalism. Antislavery and proslavery advocates developed
radically different notions of liberty from the same political principles. Ericson
unveils the complex and uncomfortable connections between slavery and freedom,
much as Edmund Morgan did for an earlier era of American history.
|
|
"A
political scientist, Ericson modifies and extends the
'liberal consensus' thesis proposed by Louis Hartz in the
1950s." |
|
|
|
A political scientist, Ericson
modifies and extends the liberal consensus thesis proposed by Louis
Hartz in the 1950s. Like Hartz, he American believes that liberal ideas synthesized
political thought and were, therefore, primary compared to other intellectual
traditions such as that even the republicanism and Protestantism. Ericson goes
farther than Hartz in arguing proslavery movement, so easily dismissed as merely
attacking the reactionary and racist, presented coherent liberal arguments in
defense of slavery, just as antislavery activists did in institution. maximized
the Both movements appealed to concepts of personal freedom, consensual government,
and private property ownership to claim that their vision of the world practical
liberty of the greatest number of men. To demonstrate this point, Ericson delivers
a precise analysis of political prominent figures in rhetoric in the writings
and speeches of six the antebellum debate over slavery: the antislavery activists
Lydia Maria Child, Dew, George Frederick Douglass, and Wendell Phillips and
the proslavery advocates Thomas R. Fitzhugh, and James H. Hammond. Ericson and
liberties to describes the emergence and evolution of an antislavery liberalism
that envisioned the progressive extension of equal rights all Americans and
a proslavery liberalism that redefined such progress as a declension toward
the social anarchy of a
state of nature (p. 36).
For example, Child highlighted the
tension between slavery and freedom, calling slavery a
cancer that threatened the national security and
economic prosperity of the country. She claimed that history
condemned the institution for blocking inevitable progress toward
liberty and equality for all people. Douglass agreed, dismissing
slavery as an anachronism. In his famous Fourth of July oration
of 1852, Douglass argued that continual progress in communication
and commerce increasingly exposed the hypocrisy of the
institution and the terrible inequities and injustices it
perpetuated. Phillips was a disunionist who believed that only
separation from the South could protect the North from the evil
effects of slavery and the pernicious political attacks of the
Southern slavocracy. He also hoped that disunion, or at least the
threat of disunion, would encourage the South to dismantle the
institution.
In the second half of his book,
Ericson turns to the proslavery supporters and presents what
likely will be his most controversial ideas. Dew, Fitzhugh, and
Hammond, each in their own way, tried to portray themselves as
the progressive liberals, arguing that not only did slavery not
retard progress but that it actually advanced the special
historical mission of the United States. In Cannibals All! or
Slaves without Masters, published in 1857, Fitzhugh
criticized Northern society for its allegedly high rates of
crime, violence, poverty, and civil unrest. He defended slavery
as an essential protective institution that brought order,
safety, and prosperity to Southern society. For Fitzhugh, then,
slavery was a superior social and economic institution compared
to the unstable arrangements in the North, and it was also more
liberal in that it supposedly united the interests of masters and
slaves. Hammond argued that abolitionists failed to understand
that slaves exchanged a portion of their natural liberty for a
more secure form of civil liberty. He believed that antislavery
agitators, who claimed to be progressive, were in fact only
agents of destruction. In the end, Ericson contends, the failure
of these proslavery arguments represented a failure of Southern
power more than a failure of political rhetoric. Although the
Civil War eventually destroyed the institution, in the decades
before the war the proslavery position became a potent and
effective ideological force in the South.
Ericsons concentrated, even
dense, analysis moves swiftly, devoting little more than 100
pages to the actual writings and speeches of the six participants
in the debate over slavery. He illuminates the nature and
development of American liberalism in the antebellum period,
revealing a common yet flexible political heritage that resulted
in diverse expressions of liberal ideas. At the same time,
Ericson provides little context for the authors, their works, and
the history of the antislavery and proslavery movements, assuming
a familiarity on the part of readers with the political and
social debates of the era and the intellectual origins of
American notions of liberty. Due in part to this tight focus,
some significant questions remain unexplored. Ericson, for
example, does not examine the connections between liberalism and
Protestantism, although most of the authors he treats mobilized
or responded to religious arguments to support their positions.
His claim that religious ideas were secondary to liberal concepts
could use stronger support, particularly given that so many
scholars since Max Weber have posited a strong link. Another
issue is that the proslavery arguments seem much more convoluted
and strained than the antislavery arguments. It is difficult not
to conclude that judgments about racial inferiority form the
critical intellectual foundation for proslavery liberalism. If
so, what does such a conclusion say about Ericsons overall
thesis that liberalism provided the most basic intellectual
material for both proslavery and antislavery positions?
Nevertheless, Ericsons clear and compelling analysis should
provoke further investigation of these issues, perhaps in some
instances following his creative blueprint for comparative study
of antislavery and proslavery rhetoric.
Tracy Neal Leavelle, Smith
College
© 2001 by The Journal
of Southern Religion. All rights reserved. ISSN 1094-5234